Rated voting

(Redirected from Cardinal voting)

Rated voting refers to any electoral system which allows the voter to give each candidate an independent evaluation, typically a rating or grade.[1] These are also referred to as cardinal, evaluative, or graded voting systems.[citation needed]Cardinal methods (based on cardinal utility) and ordinal methods (based on ordinal utility) are the two modern categories of voting systems.[2][3][4]

A theoretical ballot with the instructions "Rate each between negative ten and ten." There are five options, each one with a number corresponding to it. The numbers, from top to bottom, are seven, ten, negative three, zero, and ten.
On a rated ballot, the voter may rate each choice independently.
A theoretical ballot with the instructions "Vote for any number of options." Two choices are marked, three are not. There is no difference between the markings.
An approval voting ballot does not require ranking or exclusivity.

Variants

A majority judgment ballot is based on grades like those used in schools.

There are several voting systems that allow independent ratings of each candidate. For example:

In addition, every cardinal system can be converted into a proportional or semi-proportional system by using Phragmen's voting rules or Thiele's voting rules. Examples include:

Relationship to rankings

Ratings ballots can be converted to ranked/preferential ballots, assuming equal ranks are allowed. For example:

Rating (0 to 99)Preference order
Candidate A99First
Candidate B55Second
Candidate C20Third
Candidate D20Third

Analysis

Cardinal voting methods are not subject to Arrow's impossibility theorem,[9] which proves that ranked-choice voting methods can be manipulated by strategic nominations.[10] However, since one of these criteria (called "universality") implicitly requires that a method be ordinal, not cardinal, Arrow's theorem does not apply to cardinal methods.[11][10]

Others, however, argue that ratings are fundamentally invalid, because meaningful interpersonal comparisons of utility are impossible.[12] This was Arrow's original justification for only considering ranked systems,[13] but later in life he stated that cardinal methods are "probably the best."[14]

Psychological research has shown that cardinal ratings (on a numerical or Likert scale, for instance) are more valid and convey more information than ordinal rankings in measuring human opinion.[15][16][17][18]

Cardinal methods can satisfy the Condorcet winner criterion, usually by combining cardinal voting with a first stage (as in Smith//Score).

Strategic voting

The weighted mean utility theorem gives the optimal strategy for cardinal voting under most circumstances, which is to give the maximum score for all options with an above-average expected utility,[19] which is equivalent to approval voting. As a result, strategic voting with score voting often results in a sincere ranking of candidates on the ballot (a property that is impossible for ranked-choice voting, by the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem).

Most cardinal methods, including score voting and STAR, pass the Condorcet and Smith criteria if voters behave strategically.[citation needed] As a result, cardinal methods with strategic voters tend to produce results similar to Condorcet methods with honest voters.[citation needed]

See also

References